Early Hellenic Anticipations of Logocentrism and Homocentrism

Cover Page

Cite item

Full Text

Abstract

In this article, the intention of the authors is to show that hints of logocentric and homocentric views of the world, as the foundations of the modern civil era, despite the structural obstacles in their concepts, can be found in the works of the first Hellenic thinkers, and particular attention will be paid to the preserved fragments of the Pre-Socratics who are of interest for this research. The authors identified that indications of such approaches may be found in Pythagoreans, Parmenides, Empedocles, Anaxagoras, and Democritus. Still, the early Greek philosopher who most obviously anticipated the letter homocentric views was Alcmaeon of Croton. His opinion that the man is different from other animals because he alone has understanding, while other animals have sensation but do not understand, represents a sign of the statements of numerous subsequent writers that logos abilities may be allocated only to humans and that the man has ontological primacy in regard to the so-called non-human living beings.

Full Text

Western civilization, whose vision of cosmos is still prevailingly homocentric, finds the origin for its standing points in Judeo-Christian tradition and in the views of ancient Greek philosophers. The intention of the authors is to show that hints of logocentric and homocentric, i.e. anthropocentric [1] views of the world, as the foundations of the modern civil era, despite the structural obstacles in their concepts, can be found in the works of the first Hellenic thinkers, and particular attention in the paper below will be paid to the preserved fragments of the Pre-Socratics who are of interest for this research [1].

The Pythagorean Philolaus [2], in the book On Nature (Peri physeos) claims that there are four principles of rational animals (Zoion tou logiku): brain (enkephalos), heart (kardia), navel (omphalos) and genitals (aidoion). Philolaus makes a distinction between the centers of intellect and sensation (DK44B13), as far as "The head <is the location> of intellect, the heart of soul and sensations. The conclusion that ‘wise Philolaus’ (Philolaus….sophos) (DK44A14) is drawing is that the brain shows the principle of man, the heart principle of the animal, the navel principle of the plant, and the genitals the principle of all of them together, because everything flourishes and germinates from the seed".

In the notes of Alexander Polyhistor, it is said that he also found the information that to some extent opposes the general objection of Aristotle to the Pre-Socratics [2], that they do not distinguish the reason (nous) and thinking (phronesis) from sensation (aesthesis) and others aspect of the soul (phsyche). In (DL,VIII,30), we can notice that "The soul of man, he says, is divided into three parts, intelligence, reason, and passion. Intelligence and passion are possessed by other animals as well, but reason by man alone" (Λαέρτιος, Δ. Βίοι καὶ γνῶμαι τῶν ἐν φιλοσοφίᾳ εὐδοκιμησάντων ) [3] [3].

What is evident from this fragment is that the soul (phsyche), according to anonymous Pythagoreans, is the genus proximum "intelligence" (nous), "reason" (phrenas) [4] and "passion" (thumon). The seat of the soul extends from the heart to the brain. The "part" of the soul that is located in the heart is "passion," while "reason" and "intelligence" are "parts" that are in the brain [5]. The particularity of man's status is also manifested by the conclusion that "intelligence" and "passion" are "parts" of soul that is deadly and decaying, while "reason" is "part" of the soul that is immortal and undecaying.

Parmenides's "The Way of Truth" in the poem On Nature (Peri physeos), then, presents a sort of research on the real nature of reality and the relation of that reality to sensible phenomena. The main purpose of Eleatism, the preservation of beings, could only be achieved by the complete determination of the whole as immovable, full, indivisible, eternal... If the senses speak contrary to what is obtained by the logos, it might be said in the Hegelian manner, then so much the worse for the senses. Eleatic ontology, primarily, provides a true model of the existing, it exposes the structure of reality that is always the same and which cannot be observed by the senses. The mental reality is true regardless of the fact that it can be inaccessible to sight so much that its expression can cause confusion in the opinion. The Eleatics showed that truth Peri physeos does not have to be on the side of what is sensibly appearing, i.e. of what is most easily presented by senses. The persistence and manifestation of truth, moreover, is in contradiction with the unsteadfastness and unreliability of sensory knowledge, so it is primarily in the sphere of thought [4]. In the prologue of his poem, Parmenides emphasizes the immutability of the rationally understood truth as we can see in fragment (DK28B1.28-30.) "It is right that you learn all things – both the unshaken heart of well-persuasive Truth and the beliefs of mortals, in which there is no true trust" [5].

The most famous Eleatic philosopher in fragment 7 (DK28B7) says "Do not let habit, rich in experience, compel you along this route to direct an aimless eye and an echoing ear and tongue, but judge by reasoning (logos) the much-contested examination spoken by me" [6]. The real subject of knowledge for Parmenides is the domain of the logos. On the basis of the prologue of the poem On Nature, it can be implicitly concluded that one man ("philosopher of nature" (physicos philosophos), as Parmenides is named in DK28A11) acquired a privileged position in an unexplainable way, the truth is primarily in regards to other mortal people [6].

In Empedocles scripts, a century later, it is also possible to notice a contradiction between the fragmentary insight of the senses, i.e. sensation (aistheseos) and synthetic insight that arises by means of thinking i.e. logos (logos), which in some sense is synesthetic. Therefore he invited his disciple Pausanias (DK31B3.9-13) to act this way: "But come, look with every means of apprehension, in whatever way each thing is clear, not holding any sight more in trust than <what comes> through hearing" [7], "or loud-sounding hearing above the things made clear by the tongue, and do not at all hold back trust in any of the other limbs, wherever there is a channel for understanding, but understand each thing in whatever way it is clear" [7]. Although the Sicilian believes that all living beings are thinking (phronesis) (DK31B110. DK28A46. DK28B16), he still makes a gradation and, through a kind of hierarchy of life, humans are above animals and animals are above plants. Within the human race, there is also a gradation according to this "sage of Acragas" (Acragantinos Sophos) (DK31B134). The souls of those wise men who have come to one step from deification assume the highest forms of humanity. Medicine men, poets, doctors and rulers of other people are free from human problems and share a table with other immortals (DK31B146, DK31B147). Empedocles thought he possessed most of the above characteristics, so it is no wonder that in one sentence (DK31B112.4.) he speaks of himself as an immortal god no longer a mortal (DK31B146. Kaluđerović, Ž. "Sicilian Muse" and Ensouled Beings. forthcoming).

The fact that things are neither simple in Anaxagoras works may be seen from his qualifications of the driving force or mind. Nous in his fragments has many features of the abstract principle [8] (DK59B12) considering that "The other things have a share of everything, but Nous is unlimited and self-ruling and has been mixed with no thing, but is alone itself by itself. ... For it is the finest of all things and the purest, and indeed it maintains all discernment (gnōmē) about everything and has the greatest strength. And Nous has control over all things that have soul, both the larger and the smaller. And Nous controlled the whole revolution, so that it started to revolve in the beginning. ... nothing is completely separated off or dissociated one from the other except Nous" [9].

The philosopher from Clazomenae proves that man's mental powers are superior to the physical power of animals [8]. Anaxagoras, following the work of Diodorus, says that humans will master animals through unique experience (empeirai), memory (mnemei), wisdom (sophiai) and art (techni) (DK59B21b). The confirmation of this thesis can also be found in the well-known Aristotle's view in the Parts of Animals (Peri Zoon morion) (687a7-12). According to this interpretation, Anaxagoras considers that man is the most intelligent of all living beings (phronimotaton einai ton zoon anthropon), and as the reason for this he states the fact that man has hands (to kheiras ekhein) [9].

Sextus Empiricus, then, states that according to Democritus who was some forty years younger than Anaxagoras, there are two kinds of knowledge (gnoseis) [10], one of which is acquired by senses (aistheseon) and the other by understanding (dianoias). The knowledge gained by reason "the Mocker" (Gelasinos) (DK68A2. DK68A21. DK68A40. DK68C3) calls a legitimate one and attributes certainty to it in the study of truth, and the one acquired by the senses Abderitian considers the bastard and does not attribute certainty to it in finding out the truth (DK68A105. DK67A30.

Consult: DK68A135(58)). Then, he elaborates the superiority of the true knowledge and adds (DK68B11) "When the bastard one is unable to see or hear or smell or taste or grasp by touch any further in the direction of smallness, but <we need to go still further> toward what is fine, <then the legitimate one enables us to carry on>" [10].

Democritus (and Epicurus) considers (DK68A105) that the soul has two "parts" (DK68A105) one rational (logikon) located in the chest and the unreasoning one (alogon), which is scattered throughout the body. The "part" of the soul that is suitable for guiding "Wisdom" (Sophia) (DK68A2) places in the head. The mind is the concentration of the soul in the head, i.e., the brain, similarly to the views of Anaxagoras (DK59A108), Diogenes of Apollonia [11], Alcmaeon, and later of Plato. Based on this, it can be concluded that the soul, according to Abderitian, is mind in the narrow sense, and that senses are something that is not a soul or something that is a lower form of the soul.

Although Democritus says that the need for posterity stems from the nature of all living beings, he, at the same time, thinks that a certain distinction between humans and animals should be established. The specific feature of the humans is that they are the only ones among the beings who have souls who think that some gain actually comes from offspring (DK68B278). In addition, in its "ethical" fragments [11], an author "who seems to have thought about everything" [12] (outos d’ eoike men peri apanton phrontisai) (GC315a35) (Trans. Ž. Kaluđerović) emphasizes another characteristic of humans, which suggests not only the difference between humans and animals, but also the difference between the Greeks and barbarians, which can be sublimed in the term paideia (DK68B33, DK68B179, DK68B180, DK68B181, DK68B182, DK68B183, DK68B185, DK68B187) [13]. The Hellenes know the value of upbringing and education (paideia) for the transformation of human beings, which, according to the teachings that came out primarily from the Socrates' reception, peaks in philosophy. The shaping of a person in line with a certain sense and purpose through paideia also allows the creation of a man's "other nature", which is, in fact, his "first nature". Democritus observes that the mere natural existence of man is not the state in which he should remain, and that man as seen from his own vision represents a special event in the cosmos.

The particularity of man is expressed through his discernment that his own spiritual existence is represented as a non-natural, second-natural or as the highest point of his natural existence, that is, as a path of departure from natural existence.

A Pre-Socratic philosopher, however, most clearly anticipated a homocentric standpoint Alcmaeon of Croton believed that sensation (aisthesin) is a result of the interaction of dissimilar (me…omoioi) things (DK31A86.1). At the same time, he "first determines the difference between men and animals" [14] (men proton phphorizei ten pros ta zoia diaphoran) (DK24A5) (Trans. J. Barnes). Alcmaeon claimed that man is different from other "animals" because he alone has understanding, while other "animals" have sensation but do not understand. Crotonian puts this in the following words (DK24B1a): "He says that men differ from the other animals because they alone understand, whereas the others perceive but do not understand" [12].

Unlike the opinion of other Pre-Socratics (DK31B103, DK31B110), according to Alcmaeon, there is no equality between thinking and sensation. That writer of the first ‘treatise on nature’ (physicon logon) (DL,VIII,83) was right is visible from Aristotle's statement, without referring directly to the views of Crotonian, which states that the sensation is universal in the animal world, the thinking is found in only a small division of it [15].

"The founder of empirical psychology" (Burnet) correctly concluded that the brain, and not the heart is the centre of all sensory activities in the human organism (DK24A5) (Trans. Ž. Kaluđerović) [16]: as far as "All the senses are connected with the brain in some way" (DK24A8. DK24A13. DK24A10) [17].

Perhaps Crotonian influenced Plato with this attitude, who describes him, also without mentioning the name, as saying that knowledge comes from the stability of memory and opinion, while memory and opinion come from hearing, sight and smell with the mediation of the brain (Phaedo (Phaidon (e peri phyches) 96b) [18]. Not only that in Alcmaeon's view there is a difference between thinking and sensation, but he also anticipates Stagirites' own theory of the development of higher functions [13], somewhat improving it by the identification of the brain as the centre of sensation [19].

The criterion of differentiation between humans and animals, which Alcmaeon states, is a kind of negation of his possible belief in the migrations of the soul (panliggenesia) [14] [20], but also a hint of later homocentric i.e. anthropocentric[15] claims about the ontological primacy of man in regard to other living beings.

Additional info

Funding source. This study was not supported by any external sources of funding.

Competing interests. The author declares that they have no competing interests.

Дополнительная информация

Источник финансирования. Авторы заявляют об отсутствии внешнего финансирования при проведении исследования.

Конфликт интересов. Авторы декларирует отсутствие явных и потенциальных конфликтов интересов, связанных с публикацией настоящей статьи.

 

1 Parts of this paper have been published in previous years in several shorter or longer editions and interpretations. It would be difficult to list all the changes, especially those related to the content and style we made in the edited version of the work. The changes were made to minimise occasional digressions and introduce necessary clarifications caused by our subsequent insights due to the availability of additional literature, as well as for the purpose of a clearer and more fluid presentation.

2 Met.1009a38–1010a15.

3 URL: http://www.mikrosapoplous.gr/dl/dl.html (date accessed: 1.11.2022).

4 Met. 986b31-33. GC325a13-14.

5 Curd, P. (ed.). A Presocratic Reader. Indianapolis, Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 2011, p. p. 57, B1.28–30. Diels, H., Kranz, W. Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker I. Zürich. Hildesheim, Weidmann, 1985, s. s. 230, B1.28–30. (In German). See: DK28B5.

6 Curd, P. (ed.). A Presocratic Reader. Indianapolis, Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 2011, p. 59, B7. Diels, H., Kranz, W. Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker I. Zürich . Hildesheim, Weidmann, 1985, s. 234–235, B7. (In German).

7 Curd, P. (ed.). A Presocratic Reader. Indianapolis, Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 2011, p. 81, B3.9-13. Diels, H., Kranz, W. Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker I. Zürich . Hildesheim, Weidmann, 1985, s. 310-311, B3.9-13. (In German). Consult: Wright, M. R. Empedocles The Extant Fragments. Indianapolis, Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 1995, p. 162. DK28B7.4–5. DK28B6.6-7

8 Betegh, G. The Derveni Papyrus. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2008, p. 281. DK21B25. DK22B32. DK22B41. DK22B108. Compare: Fritz, K. v. Nous, Noein, and Their Derivatives in Pre-Socratic Philosophy (Excluding Anaxagoras). In The Pre-Socratics. Alexander P. D. Mourelatos (ed.). New York, Anchor Press/Doubleday, 1974, pp. 23–85. Barnes, J. The Presocratic Philosophers Volume 2. London, Henley and Boston, Rotledge & Kegan Paul, 1979, pp. 103–110.

9 Curd, P. (ed.). A Presocratic Reader. Indianapolis, Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 2011, p. 104, B12. Diels, H., Kranz, W. Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker I. Zürich . Hildesheim, Weidmann, 1985, s. 37-39, B12. (In German). See: Met.984b15–19. Furley, D. The Greek Cosmologists I. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2006, p. 64.

10 Curd, P. (ed.). A Presocratic Reader. Indianapolis, Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 2011, p. 122, B11. Diels, H., Kranz, W. Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker I. Zürich . Hildesheim, Weidmann, 1985, s. 141, B11. (In German). See: Hussey, E. The Presocratics. Indianapolis, Bristol Classical Press, 1995, pp. 111–113. DK68A111.

11 Kahn, C. H. Democritus and the Origins of Moral Psychology. In The American Journal of Philology, 1985, Vol. 106, No. 1, p. 1. Kaluđerović, Ž., Jašić, O., Kaluđerović Mijartović, Z. Dike – sleđenje ethosa i nomosa. In Živa baština, 2021, Vol. VII, br. 25, pp. 72–81. [Electronic resource]. https://bastinadu-hovnosti.com/wp-content/uploads/2022/05/Dike-%E2%80%93-slijedjenje-ethosa-i-nomosa.pdf (date accessed: 7.11.2022). (In Bosnian).

12 Barnes, J. Early Greek Philosophy. London, Penguin Books Ltd, 2001, p. 38. Diels, H., Kranz, W. Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker I. Zürich. Hildesheim, Weidmann, 1985, s. 215, B1a. DK24A5. (In German). Consult: Allan, D. J. The Philosophy of Aristotle. Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1979, pp. 45–46.

13 Met.I.1. An.Post.II.19. EN1039b15 and further. De morb. sacro, 17.

14 DK24A1. DK24A12. Phaedr.245c. Nom.895e–896a. De An.403b28-29. De An.404a20–25. De An.405a29–32. See: DK24B2; DK22B103; DK22C1; Tim.43D–E; Phys.264b27–28

15 Pol.1256b15-22. Singer, P. Animal Liberation. New York, Open Road Integrated Media, Inc., 2015, pp. 276-277. Consult: De An.414b18-19. De An.415a7-8. PA656a8. PA656a12-13. PA686a25-31. PA687a4-5. Top.102a20. Top.142b26. Mem.453a8. HA488b24-25. See: Καλουτζέροβιτς, Ζ. Ο Δάσκαλος Αυτών που Γνωρίζουν – Και Όσων Αγνοούν, forthcoming. (In Greek)

×

About the authors

Zeliko Kaluderovic

University of Novi Sad

Author for correspondence.
Email: zeljko.kaludjerovic@ff.uns.ac.rs
ORCID iD: 0000-0002-6572-4160

Professor of Ancient Greek Philosophy, Ethics, Ethics of Journalism and Bioethics at the Faculty of Philosophy, Novi Sad University, Novi Sad, Serbia; Professor of the Department of Philosophy and Sociology of the Faculty of Philosophy of the University, Tuzla, Bosnia and Herzegovina; Director of the Center for Bioethics of the Department of Philosophy of the Faculty of Philosophy of Novi SadUniversity of the Garden, Honorary Doctor of the Athens National and Kapodistrian University, Greece

Serbia, Novi Sad

Zorika Kaluderovic-Mijartovic

Афинский национальный университет имени Каподистрии

Email: zmijartovic@philosophy.uoa.gr
ORCID iD: 0000-0001-9315-5789

философский факультет на кафедре философии философского факультета, Нови-Садский Университет, г. Нови-Сад, Сербия; магистр, аспирант на кафедре философии философского факультета Афинского Национального и Каподистрийского университета, Греция

Greece, Афины

Orkhan Yashic

Университет Тузлы

Email: orhanjasic@yahoo.com
ORCID iD: 0000-0001-7810-7850

an Assistant Professor at the Department of Philosophy at the Faculty of Humanities and Social Sciences at the University of Tuzla, Bosnia and Herzegovina; teacher of courses in ethics, bioethics, history of medieval Philosophy and German Classical Philosophy

Bosnia and Herzegovina, Тузла

References

  1. Čović A., Krznar T. (eds.). Čovjek i priroda u bioetičkoj paradigmi. Zagreb, Filozofski fakultet Sveučilišta u Zagrebu, Odsjek za filozofiju – Katedra za etiku, 2008. (in Croatian).
  2. Kahn C.H. Pythagoras and the Pythagoreans. Indianapolis/Cambridge, Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 2001. 23 p.
  3. Laertius D. The Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers. VIII, 30. URL: https://en.wikisource.org/wiki/Lives_ of_the_Eminent_Philosophers/Book_VIII (accessed: 01.11.2022).
  4. Liddell H.G., Scott R., Jones H.S. A Greek-English Lexicon. Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1996. 1954 p.
  5. The lives and opinions of eminent philosophers. By Diogenes Laërtius. URL: https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/ 57342/pg57342-images.html#Footnote_113 (accessed: 2.11.2022).
  6. Kaluđerović Ž. Parmenidova poema i teškoće kauzalne shematike. Godišnjak Filozofskog fakulteta u Novom Sadu. 2012;XXXVII-1:359–372. URL: https://godisnjak.ff.uns.ac.rs/ index.php/gff/article/view/205/217 (accessed: 3.11.2022). (In Serbian).
  7. Kirk G.S., Raven J.E. The Presocratic Philosophers. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1971. 325 p. Compare: DK22B101a.
  8. DK59B12. De plantis (Περὶ φυτῶν) (815b16-17). Kaluđerović Ž., Jašić O., Miljević A. Slojevitost zbiljnosti physikotatosa iz Klazomene. Europski časopis za bioetiku = JAHR European Journal of Bioethics. 2020;11/2;22:381–396. URL: https://hrcak.srce.hr/ file/365766 (accessed: 04.11.2022). (In Croatian).
  9. Burnet J. Early Greek Philosophy. Cleveland and New York, The World Publishing Company, 1962. 272 p. Compare: Xen. Mem. 1.4.11, 1.4.14.
  10. Windelband, W. Geschichte der Philosophie. Beograd, BOOK & MARSO, 2007. 77 p. (In Serbian) URL: https://archive.org/details/geschichtederphi00wind/page/78/mode/2up (accessed: 5.11.2022) (In German).
  11. Kaluđerović Ž. Anaksimenov i Diogenov animatizam. Filozofska istraživanja. 2016;141;36(1):75–88. URL: https:// hrcak.srce.hr/file/244763 (date accessed: 6.11.2022). (In Croatian).
  12. Aristotle. On Generation and Corruption. The Complete Works of Aristotle. I. Jonathan Barnes (ed.). Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1991, p. 514. (In Ancient Greek).
  13. Jaeger W. PAIDEIA. Berlin, De Gruyter, 1973 (Reprint 2010). (In German).
  14. Barnes J. Early Greek Philosophy. London, Penguin Books Ltd, 2001. 38 p.
  15. Aristotle. On the Soul. The Complete Works of Aristotle. I. Jonathan Barnes (ed.). (In Ancient Greek).
  16. Guthrie W.K.C. A History of Greek Philosophy II. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1965. 349 p. DL,VIII, 83.
  17. Diels H., Kranz W. Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker I. Zürich. Hildesheim, Weidmann, 1985. 212 p. (In German).
  18. Zemelka A.M. Alcmaeon of Croton-Father of Neuroscience? Brain, Mind and Senses in the Alcmaeon’s Study. Journal of Neurology and Neuroscience. 2017;8(3);190:1—5. URL: https://www.jneuro.com/neurology-neuroscience/alcmaeon-of-croton--father-of-neuroscience-brain-mind-and-senses-in-the-alcmaeons-study.pdf (accessed: 08.11.2022).
  19. Sorabji R. Animal Minds and Human Morals. Ithaca, New York, Cornell University Press, 1995. 9 p.
  20. Kaluđerović Ž., Jašić O. Pitagorejska i arapska recepcija ne-ljudskih živih bića. Nova prisutnost = New presence. 2015;13(1):25–33. URL: https://hrcak.srce.hr/file/201998 (date accessed: 9.11.2022). (In Croatian).

Supplementary files

Supplementary Files
Action
1. JATS XML

Copyright (c) 2023 Kaluderovic Z., Kaluderovic-Mijartovic Z., Yashic O.

Creative Commons License
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License.

This website uses cookies

You consent to our cookies if you continue to use our website.

About Cookies